Pseudoelements in abelian categories #
A pseudoelement of an object X
in an abelian category C
is an equivalence class of arrows
ending in X
, where two arrows are considered equivalent if we can find two epimorphisms with a
common domain making a commutative square with the two arrows. While the construction shows that
pseudoelements are actually subobjects of X
rather than "elements", it is possible to chase these
pseudoelements through commutative diagrams in an abelian category to prove exactness properties.
This is done using some "diagram-chasing metatheorems" proved in this file. In many cases, a proof
in the category of abelian groups can more or less directly be converted into a proof using
pseudoelements.
A classic application of pseudoelements are diagram lemmas like the four lemma or the snake lemma.
Pseudoelements are in some ways weaker than actual elements in a concrete category. The most
important limitation is that there is no extensionality principle: If f g : X ⟶ Y
, then
∀ x ∈ X, f x = g x
does not necessarily imply that f = g
(however, if f = 0
or g = 0
,
it does). A corollary of this is that we can not define arrows in abelian categories by dictating
their action on pseudoelements. Thus, a usual style of proofs in abelian categories is this:
First, we construct some morphism using universal properties, and then we use diagram chasing
of pseudoelements to verify that is has some desirable property such as exactness.
It should be noted that the Freyd-Mitchell embedding theorem gives a vastly stronger notion of pseudoelement (in particular one that gives extensionality). However, this theorem is quite difficult to prove and probably out of reach for a formal proof for the time being.
Main results #
We define the type of pseudoelements of an object and, in particular, the zero pseudoelement.
We prove that every morphism maps the zero pseudoelement to the zero pseudoelement (apply_zero
)
and that a zero morphism maps every pseudoelement to the zero pseudoelement (zero_apply
).
Here are the metatheorems we provide:
- A morphism
f
is zero if and only if it is the zero function on pseudoelements. - A morphism
f
is an epimorphism if and only if it is surjective on pseudoelements. - A morphism
f
is a monomorphism if and only if it is injective on pseudoelements if and only if∀ a, f a = 0 → f = 0
. - A sequence
f, g
of morphisms is exact if and only if∀ a, g (f a) = 0
and∀ b, g b = 0 → ∃ a, f a = b
. - If
f
is a morphism anda, a'
are such thatf a = f a'
, then there is some pseudoelementa''
such thatf a'' = 0
and for everyg
we haveg a' = 0 → g a = g a''
. We can think ofa''
asa - a'
, but don't get too carried away by that: pseudoelements of an object do not form an abelian group.
Notations #
We introduce coercions from an object of an abelian category to the set of its pseudoelements and from a morphism to the function it induces on pseudoelements.
These coercions must be explicitly enabled via local instances:
attribute [local instance] objectToSort homToFun
Implementation notes #
It appears that sometimes the coercion from morphisms to functions does not work, i.e.,
writing g a
raises a "function expected" error. This error can be fixed by writing
(g : X ⟶ Y) a
.
References #
- [F. Borceux, Handbook of Categorical Algebra 2][borceux-vol2]
This is just composition of morphisms in C
. Another way to express this would be
(Over.map f).obj a
, but our definition has nicer definitional properties.
Equations
Instances For
Two arrows f : X ⟶ P
and g : Y ⟶ P
are called pseudo-equal if there is some object
R
and epimorphisms p : R ⟶ X
and q : R ⟶ Y
such that p ≫ f = q ≫ g
.
Equations
- One or more equations did not get rendered due to their size.
Instances For
Pseudoequality is transitive: Just take the pullback. The pullback morphisms will be epimorphisms since in an abelian category, pullbacks of epimorphisms are epimorphisms.
The arrows with codomain P
equipped with the equivalence relation of being pseudo-equal.
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.setoid P = { r := CategoryTheory.Abelian.PseudoEqual P, iseqv := ⋯ }
Instances For
A Pseudoelement
of P
is just an equivalence class of arrows ending in P
by being
pseudo-equal.
Equations
Instances For
A coercion from an object of an abelian category to its pseudoelements.
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.objectToSort = { coe := fun (P : C) => CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement P }
Instances For
A coercion from an arrow with codomain P
to its associated pseudoelement.
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.overToSort = { coe := Quot.mk (CategoryTheory.Abelian.PseudoEqual P) }
Instances For
If two elements are pseudo-equal, then their composition with a morphism is, too.
A morphism f
induces a function pseudoApply f
on pseudoelements.
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.pseudoApply f = Quotient.map (fun (g : CategoryTheory.Over P) => CategoryTheory.Abelian.app f g) ⋯
Instances For
A coercion from morphisms to functions on pseudoelements.
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.homToFun = { coe := CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.pseudoApply }
Instances For
Applying a pseudoelement to a composition of morphisms is the same as composing with each morphism. Sadly, this is not a definitional equality, but at least it is true.
Composition of functions on pseudoelements is composition of morphisms.
In this section we prove that for every P
there is an equivalence class that contains
precisely all the zero morphisms ending in P
and use this to define the zero
pseudoelement.
The arrows pseudo-equal to a zero morphism are precisely the zero morphisms.
The zero pseudoelement is the class of a zero morphism.
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.pseudoZero = ⟦CategoryTheory.Over.mk 0⟧
Instances For
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.hasZero = { zero := CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.pseudoZero }
Equations
- CategoryTheory.Abelian.Pseudoelement.instInhabited = { default := 0 }
The pseudoelement induced by an arrow is zero precisely when that arrow is zero.
Morphisms map the zero pseudoelement to the zero pseudoelement.
The zero morphism maps every pseudoelement to 0.
An extensionality lemma for being the zero arrow.
A monomorphism is injective on pseudoelements.
A morphism that is injective on pseudoelements only maps the zero element to zero.
A morphism that only maps the zero pseudoelement to zero is a monomorphism.
An epimorphism is surjective on pseudoelements.
A morphism that is surjective on pseudoelements is an epimorphism.
Two morphisms in an exact sequence are exact on pseudoelements.
If two morphisms are exact on pseudoelements, they are exact.
If two pseudoelements x
and y
have the same image under some morphism f
, then we can form
their "difference" z
. This pseudoelement has the properties that f z = 0
and for all
morphisms g
, if g y = 0
then g z = g x
.
If f : P ⟶ R
and g : Q ⟶ R
are morphisms and p : P
and q : Q
are pseudoelements such
that f p = g q
, then there is some s : pullback f g
such that fst s = p
and snd s = q
.
Remark: Borceux claims that s
is unique, but this is false. See
Counterexamples/Pseudoelement.lean
for details.
In the category Module R
, if x
and y
are pseudoequal, then the range of the associated
morphisms is the same.